Friday, December 30, 2011

- character, binary oppositions, meaning -

The construction of the “Other” is vital to the construction of the Self. Ferdinand de Saussure argued that meaning depends on the difference between opposites. Meaning, argued Saussure, is relational. It is the “difference” that carries meaning. These binary opositions - white/black, day/night, masculine/feminine, citizen/alien have the great value of capturing the diversity of the world within their either/or extremes.

In everyday life, the marking of difference is the basis of the symbolic order which we call culture. Culture depends on giving things meaning by assigning them to different positions within a classificatory system. As Stuart Hall emphasizes, binary oppositions may be useful as a beginning point for interpreting our world, but they are also a crude and reductionist way of establishing meaning and often give rise to stereotyping. In his essay on stereotyping, Dyer argues that, without the use of types, it would be difficult, if not impossible, to make sense of the world. We understand the world by referring individual objects, people or events in our heads to the general classificatory schemes into which - according to our culture - they fit.

In other words, we understand “the particular” in terms of its “type.” We come to “know” something about a person by thinking of the roles which he or she performs: is he/she a parent, a child, a worker, a lover, boss, or an old age pensioner? We assign him/her to the membership of different groups, according to class, gender, age group, nationality, “race”, linguistic group, sexual preference and so on. We order him/her in terms of personality type - is he/she a happy, serious, depressed, scatter-brained, over-active kind of person? Our picture of who the person “is” is built up out of the information we accumulate from positioning him/her within these different orders of typification. In broad terms, then, “a type is any simple, vivid, memorable, easily grasped and widely recognized characterization in which a few traits are foregrounded and change or "development" is kept to a minimum”.

- deconstruction -


In order to avoid misinterpretation of reality, and avoid stereotypes in its representation, we must deconstruct hierarchy of binary oppositions. But Jonathan Culler notes that deconstruction disrupts not only the hierarchy, it disrupts the opposition itself. Derrida develops a programme of reading texts that sees beyond the narrow confines of binary opposites and thus to disturb the reliance on hierarchical oppositions. He believes that the critical metaphysical tradition which extends from Plato to modern times, that includes Marxism and structuralism is insufficient.

The philosophical project of deconstruction attempts at charting how key terms, motifs, and characters are defined by binary oppositions within a text, how the oppositions are hierarchical and demonstrating that these oppositions are unstable, reversible, and mutually dependent on one another. Then we may be able to show how each term in the opposition is joined to its companion by a complex network of arteries. Derrida claims that the line ordinarily drawn between the two terms is shown to be a political and not natural reality.







Thursday, December 15, 2011




- otherness, alterity, character - 

"Je est un autre" [I is another] 
(Arthur Rimbaud in letter to Paul Demeny on 15 mai 1871) 

"The true life is absent". "But we are in the world ".
(Emanuel Levinas: Totality and Infinity) 


The first sentence by Levinas is a paraphrase of Rimbaud and the second an allusion to Heidegger, who characterises human life as being-in-the-world. Being-in-the-world means that we have needs and wants that we can fulfil and enjoy, and yet there is something that does not fit into this world, it is beyond or rather to big to fit into this world it overflows it. This 'it' is the good, the infinite, the other. 


creation of otherness - step by step

- The distinction between self and other is a primary tool by which we make order out of the chaos of our daily perceptions. 

- The construction of Alterity (Otherness) sees not individuals, but classes and categories. Constructing entire categories of individuals as other than people, other than human, it proposes that other than ourselves = less than ourselves. Victor Frankenstein, character from the movie and the book, constructed "less than human" to equal "sentient individuals in human form created in the laboratory rather than by sexual intercourse." But his creature, at least in the novel, rather than having a tabula rasa for a brain, had an innate language instinct and cognitive intelligence, even though he was never nurtured or given a name. The category of less than human has historically been defined to include different subcategories at different times, using as markers gender, race, class, ethnicity, language, sexuality, national origin, culture, religion, type of intelligence. 

- The construction of Alterity (Otherness) is not the same thing as prejudice or the various "isms"--- for example, racism, sexism, classism. It is an early step in the process by which we create a semblance of social order. First we construct some group as Other. Next we project onto it those qualities we reject, fear, or disown in ourselves. Then we assign qualities to variable human individuals on the basis of their inclusion in this constructed Alterity. Once we take this step in our construction of Alterity (Otherness), then, at last, we have also created prejudice and stereotyping. 

- The final step in the construction of Alterity (Otherness) is to institutionalize these prejudices in our laws and customs. When laws, group culture, educational values, and social custom operate as if prejudices were truths, then we have racism, sexism, classism, anti-semitism. 



In Otherness in Hollywood Cinema, Michael Richardson argues that the Hollywood system has been the only national cinema with the resources and inclination to explore images of others through stories set in exotic and faraway places. He traces many of the ways in which Hollywood has constructed otherness, and discusses the extent to which those images have persisted and conditioned today’s understanding. The book examines a range of genres from the perspective of otherness, including the Western, film noir, and zombie movies and focuses on themes of wilderness, frontier, exotics, night, monsters, borders, sanctification of difference as ways of representing Otherness. 






Wednesday, November 23, 2011

- tree as a character -






I consider a tree.

I can look on it as a picture: stiff column in a stock of light, or splash of green shot with the delicate blue and silver of the background. 

I can perceive it as a movement: flowing veins on clinging, pressing pith, suck of the roots, breathing of the leaves, ceaseless commerce with earth and air - and the obscure growth itself.

I can classify it in a species and study it as a type in its structure and mode of life.

I can subdue its actual presence and form so sternly that I recognise it only as an expression of law-of the laws in accordance with which a constant opposition of forces is continually adjusted, or of those in accordance with which the component substances mingle and separate.

I can dissipate it and perpetuate it in number, in pure numerical relation.

In all this the tree remains my object, occupies space and time, and has its nature and constitution.

It can, however, also come about, if I have both will and grace, that in considering the tree I become bound up in relation to it. The tree is now no longer It. I have been seized bu the power of exclusiveness.

To effect this it is not necessary for me to give up any of the ways in wich I consider the tree. There is nothing from which I would have to turn my eyes away in order to see, and no knowledge that I would have to forget. Rather is everything, picture and movement, species and type, law and number, indivisibly united in this event.

Everything belonging to the tree is in this: its form and structure, its colours and chemical composition, its intercourse with the elements and with the stars, are all present in a single whole.

The tree is no impression, no play of my imagination, no value depending on my mood; but it is bodied over against me and has to do with me, as I with it - only in a different way.

Let no attempt be made to sap the strength from the meaning of the relation: relation is mutual.

The tree will have a consciousness, then, similar to our own? Of that I have no experience. But do you wish, through seeming to succeed in it with yourself, once again to disintegrate that which cannot be dissintegrated? I encounter no soul or dryad of the tree, but the tree itself.

(Martin Buber)












Monday, October 31, 2011


- action, hierarchy, reality -


"If in all ideology men and their circumstances appear upside down as in a camera obscura, this phenomenon arises just as much from their historical life-process as the inversion of objects on the retina does from their physical life-process." (Marx: The German Ideology) 

The idea that ideology inverts reality, expressed with camera obscura metaphor, Marx contends that reality appears upside down in ideology, much like the photographic process provides an inverted image. The inverted image is telling; it is a recognisable depiction of reality, even if it is at the same time a distorted one. This Marx metaphor is crucial for his concept of action. In order to "make things right" revolutionary action is the response that reverses social hierarchy. Cinema, with its narrative structure, in comparison to photography, poses different ideological problems, in relation to hierarchy:

"Cinema is true. A story is a lie." (Jean Epstein)

In these lines, Jean Epstein lays bare the problem posed by the very notion of a film fable. Cinema is to the art of telling stories what truth is to lying. It discards the infantile expectation for the end of the tale, with its marriage and numerous children. But, more importantly, it discards the ‘fable’ in the Aristotelian sense: the arrangement of necessary and verisimilar actions that lead the characters from fortune to misfortune, or vice versa, through the careful construction of the intrigue and denouement. Life has nothing to do with dramatic progression, but is instead a long and continuous movement made up of an infinity of micromovements. This truth about life has finally found an art capable of doing it justice, an art in which the intelligence that creates the reversals of fortune and the dramatic conflicts is subject to another intelligence, the intelligence of the machine that wants nothing, that does not construct any stories, but simply records the infinity of movements that gives rise to a drama a hundred times more intense than all dramatic reversals of fortune. 

This is why the art of moving images can overthrow the old Aristotelian hierarchy that privileged muthos—the coherence of the plot—and devalued opsis—the spectacle’s sensible effect. Cinema revokes the old mimetic order because it resolves the question of mimesis at its root—the Platonic denunciation of images, the opposition between sensible copy and intelligible model. The matter seen and transcribed by the mechanic eye, says Epstein, is equivalent to mind: a sensible immaterial matter composed of waves and corpuscles that abolishes all opposition between deceitful appearance and substantial reality. 



Thursday, October 13, 2011





- character, mimesis, marx -


A character mask (German: Charaktermaske) in the Marxian sense is a character masked or disguised with a different character. The term was used by Karl Marx in various published writings from the 1840s to the 1860s, and it is related to the classical Greek concept of mimesis (imitative representation using analogies) and the Roman concept of persona. The notion of character masks has been used by neo-Marxist and non-Marxist sociologists, philosophers and anthropologists to interpret how people relate in societies with a complex division of labour. As a critical concept, bearing character masks contrasts with the concept of "role-taking" because "social roles" do not necessarily assume the masking of behaviour, and character masks do not necessarily assume agreement with roles, or that the roles are fixed. Peter Sloterdijk comments: 

"Besides the critique of mystified consciousness, Marx's theory harbors a second far-reaching variant of ideology critique, which has shaped the critical style of Marxism, its polemical sharpness: the theory of the character mask."

The concept of character masks refers to the circumstance that, in human societies, people can take on functions in which they “act out” roles, whether voluntarily chosen, by necessity, or forced. In those roles, some or all of their true characteristics and intentions may be partly or wholly masked, so that they appear different from what they truly are - “public face” and “private thoughts, interests and emotions” diverge. This implies that persons and their relationships may no longer be quite what they seem to be, and there is a difference between their personal and functional relationships. 

Marx uses the term "character mask" analogously to a theatrical role, where the actor represents a certain interest or function. His concept is both that an identity appears differently from its true identity (it is masked or disguised), and that this difference has very real practical consequences (the mask is not simply a decoration, but performs a real function and has real effects, even independently of the mask bearer).



Saturday, October 8, 2011





- character, model, mimesis -

The image of the world around us, which we carry in our head, is just a model. Nobody in his head imagines all the world, government or country. He has only selected concepts, and relationships between them, and uses those to represent the real system." (Wright Forrester, American computer engineer and systems scientist)

The ‘model’ is the single word that appears most often in Notes on Cinematographer, written by Robert Bresson, film director. Model is also the term most evoked by critics trying to describe Bresson’s cinema language. To Bresson the model refers simply to the performer who lays bare their soul to the camera. Term "model" also has the meaning of ‘template,’ a prototype:

“Models. Mechanized outwardly, Intact, virgin within”

“An actor needs to get out of himself in order to see himself in the other person. YOUR MODELS, ONCE OUTSIDE THEMSELVES, WILL NOT BE ABLE TO GET IN AGAIN”


- true and mimesis in cinema -

According to Bresson, the true in film is not encrusted in the living persons and real objects. It is an air of truth that their images take on when you set them together in a certain order. With this remark, the mimetic relation between the imitating and the imitated, or the representation and its original, is completely overturned, such that the representation becomes originary and takes precedence over both the true and the reality.


Bresson's solution to the problem of reality and it's photographic representation consists simply in suspending the sense of the image. By the suspension of its sense, the image seems to cease function as an image. It ceases to be an image of something and withdraws to being just an image. It is thus like an ‘empty' or a flat image, apt to take on other meanings in the film. This is why Bresson prescribes: ‘Work on insignificant (non-signifying) images.'

The ‘BEING' of the model is in fact this withdrawal, this self-effacement before the camera. His being is not the identity of a self that the filmic image is apt to reproduce. This withdrawal undermines not only the identity of the model, it undermines at the same time the referent of the filmic image. With the withdrawal, the immediate sense of the image is suspended, and we are left with an ‘open' image that can take on new significations. 


"Mechanics gives rise to the unknown." (Bresson)

Mimesis, as Deleuze says, is no longer the question of ‘modern' cinema. But it is a power that ‘restores our belief in the world' in that it continuously creates our world anew as fiction.




Tuesday, September 27, 2011



- character and illusionist tradition -



Brecht believed that an actor should present a character in a way that wasn't an impersonation, rather, a narration of the actions of the character. He constantly reminded his audience that they were watching a play. According to him, if the audience developed an emotional attachment to the characters, then they could not evaluate the social realities of the play. Stanislavski's opinion was that if an actor believed he was a character, then the audience would believe this as well, and feel the emotions that the character was feeling. Acting in Brecht's Epic Theatre means that an actor is required to play characters believably without convincing either the audience or themselves that they are, indeed, the characters. There is an audible and visual distance between the actor and their character and the actors will often 'break the fourth wall' and address the audience, play multiple characters, and use exaggerated or repetitive actions to make their distance and social commentary known.

Brecht's idea (and subsequently of Walter Benjamin), was that radical work or art must oppose the illusionist mode at every level. Thus, the means of expression are itself called into question. Because the “means of expression” are ideologically determined, it is no longer sufficient to place a new “content” within the old structures of expression. Instead, the signifying system itself must be attacked, in order to overthrow the basis upon which the dominant ideological message rests. This procedure constitutes the crux of Godard’s work, particularly since 1968, and it lies similarly embedded in the films of Jean-Marie Straub. Much of Straub’s work may be elucidated in terms of a systematic “deconstruction” of the old forms of cinematic expression. The camera, in an illusionist film, is subordinated to the central dramatic characters’ movements. It pans to follow their motion, or it moves to a close up to record moments of “intensity”. Straub’s camera never pans to follow movement, but follows a logic of its own. That logic is devoted to the articulation of the material space in which the action takes place.

Where the illusionist film centers its lead actors in the frame, Straub does not. And where the illusionist film cuts when a character exits from the frame, in order to expedite the progress of the narrative, Straub frequently lets his camera rest for twenty or thirty seconds on the “empty” screen. Thus, the materiality of the space in which the characters operate is reasserted.

There is, however, a crucial difference between the austerity of Bresson, and that of Straub. Bresson pares away the non-essentials in order to enable the viewers to feel their way to the heart of the film. His end is epiphanous, transcendental. Straub’s austerity is functional. It forces the audience to think. For Straub, conscious mental activity is a prerequisite of understanding. In taking this position, he clearly stands in opposition to the mainstream of cinema’s evolution. The conventional film denies the eye’s responsibility to the mind. This filmic technique is devoted to the total creation and sustaining of illusion, in the course of which the director attempts to make the viewer forget the camera’s omnipresence and manipulation of one’s perspective. Emotional identification, in which the spectator associates with a character and thus vicariously enters the world of the film, is another staple of the “illusionist” tradition.

Straub rejects any attempt to anaesthetize the viewer’s mind. He refuses to make concessions to his audience’s expectations. We are never allowed to identify with the characters that inhabit his films. Our eyes are not glutted by sweeping camera movements or cluttered frames. We cannot enter into his worlds, but we may reflect upon them. His style’s “spareness” functions as an invitation to reflection, to analysis. Straub’s later films, in particular, create spaces in which, deliberately, nothing happens. They offer spaces in which the eye and mind are invited to interact.






Wednesday, September 14, 2011



- character, function, unmotivated action -

characters are part of every storytelling, whether it is fiction, documentary, news, reality show or theory. When characters stop looking like living men as one meet in the reality of life and history, their function takes over which creates manipulation on ideological level. 

Nevertheless, 

"The difference between truth and fiction is that fiction has to make sense." (paraphrase of Mark Twain)

In economic theory, the entrepreneurs, capitalists, landowners, workers, and consumers are not living men as one meets them in the reality of life and history. They are the embodiment of distinct functions in the market operations. Economics, in speaking of entrepreneurs, has in view not men, but a definite function. This function is not the particular feature of a special group or class of men; it is inherent in every action and burdens every actor. (Ludwig von Mises, Human Action: A Treatise on Economics)

Erich Fromm makes a distinction between individual character, which describes the richness of the character structure of an individual, and the social character which describes the emotional attitudes common to people in a social class or society. In order that a society functions adequately, their members must acquire a character structure which enables them to do what they need to do in order to prosper. It is for example expected in an authoritarian society that people are motivated to subordinate themselves to a hierarchy and fulfill selflessly the instructions brought to them. However, in the permissive consumer culture people are socialized to consume gladly and extensively. Thus the character structure in every society is formed in such a way that people can fulfill expectations quasi voluntarily.

Action is always political, as Hannah Arendt says. Louis Althusser points out that ideology always manifests itself through actions, which are "inserted into practices" (Lenin), for example, rituals, conventional behavior, and so on. Indeed, Althusser, Marxist philosopher, goes so far as to adopt Pascal's formula for belief: "Pascal says more or less: 'Kneel down, move your lips in prayer, and you will believe'". 

Action = the causation of change by the exertion of power or a natural process (dictionary definition)

- east -

Wu-wei is the principle of unmotivated action in which nonintervention in the natural course of things is to be encouraged. Action may be taken when it is spontaneous, devoid of premeditation and is appropriate to the situation. The concept of wu wei is often described as performing a selfless act but this merely exposes the background of the writer. 

The Sage is occupied with the unspoken
and acts without effort.
Teaching without verbosity,
producing without possessing,
creating without regard to result,
claiming nothing,
the Sage has nothing to lose.


- west -

"This is the mark of the act: a basic rupture in the weave of reality that opens up new possibilities and creates the space for a reconfiguration of reality itself. Like the miracle, the act is ultimately unsustainable - it cannot be reduced to, or incorporated directly within, the symbolic order. Yet it is through the act that we touch (and are touched by) the Real in such a way that the bonds of our symbolic universe are broken and that an alternative construction is enabled; reality is transformed in a Real sense. (Slavoj Zizek)




different types of action







Tuesday, August 30, 2011


- character, agency, act -


Agency is the capacity of a person or other entity to act in a world. In philosophy, the agency is considered as belonging to that agent even if that agent represents a fictitious character, or some other non-existent entity.

In certain philosophical traditions (particularly those established by Hegel and Marx), human agency is a collective, historical dynamic, rather than a function arising out of individual behavior. Hegel's Geist and Marx's universal class are idealist and materialist expressions of this idea of humans treated as social beings, organized to act in concert.

Hannah Arendt claims that it is the act of disclosure itself, the willingness to take the risk, rather than the quality of the act that actually constitutes greatness. Arendt does not think of disclosure as expression or as unmasking. Nor is disclosing exactly the same as giving information. Arendt's concern is with speech, not as the product of a set of practices or conditions, but as the act of an agent. 




Friday, August 12, 2011



- character, eudaimon, hero -



Eudaimonia (Greek: εὐδαιμονία) is a classical Greek word commonly translated as 'happiness'. Etymologically, it consists of the word "eu" ("good" or "well being") and "daimōn" ("spirit" or "minor deity", used by extension to mean one's lot or fortune). Although popular usage of the term happiness refers to a state of mind, related to joy or pleasure, eudaimonia rarely has such connotations, and the less subjective "human flourishing" is often preferred as a translation.

According to Hannah Arendt, we have lost the meaning of the ancient saying that no one can be called eudaimon before dying. We translate eudaimon as happy or blessed, but the term eudamonia indicates neither happiness nor blessedness. The word indicates rather "blessedness, but without any religious overtones, and means literally something like the well-being of the daimon who accompanies every man throughout life, who is his distinct identity, but appears and is visible only to others. (...) The essence of who someone is "can come into being only when the life departs, leaving behind nothing but a story." This unchangeable identity of the person, that only death rescues from change, renders anyone eudaimon, by giving them their story.

Arendt claimed that the disclosure of "Who somebody is or was," can be known "only by knowing the story of which he is himself the hero—his biography." In this context, the hero of a story is merely the person about whom a story is told, not someone who has achieved great things. And it appears that Arendt believed an individual can achieve some from of greatness simply by being the hero of a story in this more restricted sense.

"The hero the story discloses needs no heroic qualities... The connotation of courage,... is in fact already present in a willingness to act and speak at all, to insert one’s self into the world and begin a story of one's own."

Arendt went so far as to insist that the "extent of this original courage," that is the courage to risk disclosure, "without which action and speech and therefore, according to the Greeks, freedom, would not be possible at all, is not less great and may even be greater if the 'hero' happens to be a coward." Presumably it would take greater courage for the coward to risk disclosure because he is more likely than others to disclose what is shameful. 

This places action in a new light. As a vehicle for disclosure it need do no more than reveal the "who" of the agent, which is essentially a story or biography. "Every individual life between birth and death can eventually be told as a story with beginning and end..."


"The experience that we have of our lives from within, the story we tell ourselves about ourselves in order to account for what we are doing, is fundamentally a lie—the truth lies outside, in what we do. (Zizek)



Monday, July 4, 2011


- human character as a set of informations -




"If humans are information-processing machines, then they must have biological equipment enabling them to process binary code." (Warren McCulloch)



For McCulloch biological equipment are neurons. He believed that information moves through signals, and signals only exist if they are embodied. 




Thomas Eisner prefers metaphor of a book:

"As a consequence of recent advances in genetic engineering, [a biological species] must be viewed as ... a depository of genes that are potentially transferable. A species is not merely a hard-bound volume of the library of nature. It is also a loose-leaf book, whose individual pages, the genes, might be available for selective transfer and modification of other species." (Thomas Eisner)


The conclusions of research of two scientists are different as a result of the predominant cultural models. From mechanical, in second half of 20th century to data base in first half of 21st century. Half century that separate two scientists, produced the difference, but the similar is the importance of information in biological systems.


Tuesday, June 28, 2011

- duels in binary code: Pierrot vs Ferdinand -



Marianne: Have you killed a man before, Pierrot?
Ferdinand: My name is Ferdinand. Why do you ask?




Pierrot
01010000 01101001 01100101 01110010 01110010 01101111 01110100

1 - 50%
0 - 50%



Ferdinand 

01000110 01100101 01110010 01100100 01101001 01101110 01100001 01101110 01100100

1 - 47.2%
0 - 52.8%



Although Pierrot and Ferdinand is the same character, first name (Pierrot) is completely ambivalent in binary code with same amount of 1 and 0, while the other (Ferdinand) shows predominance of 0. Name Pierrot is more important for understanding the symbolic dimension of this character, while Ferdinand shows his real, inexplainable dimension.

Friday, June 24, 2011

- animal character's stereotypes and philosophy -

In order to make any kind of sense of the “great, blooming, buzzing confusion” of reality, in order to get a hold on the “mass of complex data that we receive from the world,” it is necessary, inescapable even, that we employ generalities, patternings, typifications. Stereotypes are simply a form of this “ordering” and in themselves need not be considered a force for evil: the stereotype sleeps within each sign after all. It is the unreflective iteration of signs that lends them their stereotypic character, and which results in increasingly rigid, sharply defined categories. The danger with stereotypes lies in allowing them to hide their limitations and partiality, in failing to appreciate that it is an incomplete picture that they paint.
Saussure’s horse and ox
There are two particular uses to which animals have been put by philosophy and critical theory that complicate the question of the stereotyped or stereotypic animal. On the one hand, writers who have clearly had no interest in animals per se have not been able to resist employing them as ciphers. A cipher is any person or thing which “fills a place, but is of no importance or worth” in its own right. The real power lying elsewhere, the cipher remains “a nonentity, a ‘mere nothing’” employed for the benefit of others (Oxford English Dictionary). Though all manner of entities are fair game, so to speak, for cipherous appropriation, literary and cultural theorists like Barthes, as well as a long history of philosophers, have been especially keen on animals. Saussure’s horse and ox are a case in point. In order to investigate language, Saussure begins his Course in General Linguistics, famously, by examining the nature of its basic unit, the linguistic sign. The sign is composed, he asserts, of two distinct but mutually dependent elements: the concept or signified (signifié) and the sound-image or signifier (signifiant). Thus, the sign for a horse, Saussure’s first cipherous animal, will comprise, on the one hand, the mental concept of a horse (“a solidhoofed perissodactyl quadruped, having a flowing mane and tail,” according to the Oxford English Dictionary), and on the other, the word “horse” (h-ō-s). Both elements, Saussure stresses, are “psychological”: the signified is not an actual horse, but the mental concept of one, and the signifier is not a physical or material sound but a “sound-image,” an “inner image” that we can recite to ourselves without actually vocalising.
The use of animals as ciphers by literary and critical theory is a particular example of the casual anthropocentrism that so often pervades these disciplines. Theorists have frequently conversed using animals, but less often do these discussions prove to be about animals. They remain invisible, metaphorical phantoms, employed merely as examples of epistemological problems, metaphysical speculations, or linguistic analyses. With the cipher, the reader disregards the animal and concentrates instead on the argument, the example, the heart of the matter. The animal used as a cipher is employed to make a point for which there is no obvious or necessary reason that this animal was chosen. On the other hand, there is a use to which animals have been widely put which entirely depends on their distinctive, characteristic presence. An index points out a particular quality or behaviour that is peculiar to the animal, and therefore intrinsic or necessary to the philosophical argument.
As George Fyler Townsend, the best known translator of Aesop into English, says of the fables: “The introduction of the animals or fictitious characters should be marked with an unexceptionable care and attention to their natural attributes, and to the qualities attributed to them by universal popular consent. The Fox should be always cunning, the Hare timid, the Lion bold, the Wolf cruel, the Bull strong, the Horse proud, and the Ass patient” 
On the other hand, however, we know that the animals in the fables are present only as impersonal instantiations of various diverse qualities. They are, as G. K. Chesterton puts it in his own introduction to the fables, “like abstractions in algebra, or like pieces in chess,” chosen over human protagonists the better to communicate the truths, or moral truisms, of the tales. Chesterton argues that it is only by stripping the tales’ protagonists of any individual personal traits that the virtues or vices that they exemplify can be made incontestably clear. A human person will therefore not do, and the animal that takes their place must be of an emblematic, even heraldic type. 
Aesop’s animal alphabet operates, then, with both indices and ciphers. The creatures may or may not be chosen for their peculiar characteristics, but they always serve as media for the time-honoured and much more important moral at the heart of the tale. In the fables, as with philosophical and theoretical texts, animals are neither ciphers nor indices. Aesop’s fox is not intrinsically one or the other, but rather functions as a cipher or as an index. The use of any given animal will tend at one time toward the cipherous, at another toward the indexical, and will many times exhibit elements of both. The more indexical the use, though, the closer we come to eliminating that rather lifeless creation, the animal in the “general singular.” It is the particularity of the animal index, or rather, the particularities of a host of indices, that serve to reanimate the lifeless ciphers and thereby help to bring about the death of “the animal.”
The potential problem for any animal that functions indexically, however, is that she or he is likely to ossify into a mere stereotype. In short, though carefully selected for some distinctive quality, indeed because this is the case, the index is still a sign, and as Barthes pointed out, “in each sign sleeps that monster: the stereotype” 
Derrida's cat
Derrida has insisted on the importance of the singular, concrete, individual animal in his own work. In “This Animal That Therefore I Am (More to Follow),” he talks about a particular, individual cat. He does not want here to concern himself with any cat that is a figure or allegory, that appears as an ambassador or representative of the “immense symbolic responsibility” with which cats have always been charged. He wants to discuss a real, actual cat, the “unsubstitutable singularity” of a particular cat, sitting now, gazing at him.
The animal in the “general singular,” says Derrida, is “a sin against rigorous thinking, vigilance, lucidity, or empirical authority”. We must look closely at faceless animal ciphers, then, and see whether they might in fact be highly individual indices. 
Derrida never tells us the name of his cat. Does the cat’s name matter? Derrida thinks so: in the very paragraph in which he marks the difference between his real cat and the symbolic cats of literature, he says “Nothing can ever take away from me the certainty that what we have here is an existence that refuses to be conceptualised. And a mortal existence, for from the moment that it has a name, its name survives it.”. This feline is not named, though, either actively (elle s’appelle) or passively (nominatur).
Derrida does not actually say that “it has a name,” of course: the reifying pronoun is an unfortunate consequence of the English translation. Derrida has pointed out to us, indeed it is relevant to the embarrassment that he feels, that his cat is a female cat, “une chatte”. But having made this specification, having drawn our attention to her gender, Derrida persists in using the “generic masculine” (un chat) that he had formerly confined to the cats of figure and allegory: he says “il a un nom.” Derrida’s cat, who has a name, though she remains unnamed, is both une chatte and un chat . Her existence both as a female cat and as an individual cat seems, by this curious conflation, temporarily to be overlooked.These oversights, if such they are, do not take anything from Derrida’s important argument that it is individual animals who demand fresh thought about animals. They point, rather, to the persistence with which forms of discourse, philosophical and otherwise, can work against the attempt to use words that are genuinely naked.




(excerpts from Tom Tyler's "Quia Ego Nominor Leo: Barthes, Stereotypes and Aesop’s Animals")



Monday, June 20, 2011



- stereotypes of animal characters -

Animal characters in cinema, TV and other media depict human characteristics via anthropomorphism.

There are stereotypical traits which commonly tend to be associated with particular species. Often these are simply exaggerations of real aspects or behaviours of the creature in question, while other times the stereotype is taken from mythology and the true origins are forgotten. Many modern stereotypes of animals have a long tradition dating back to Aesop's Fables, which drew upon sources that included Ancient Egyptian animal tales.

Many animal stereotypes are unfair to impose upon actual animals in nature, since moral is not inherent to any other species but human. So we can conclude that animals are used in cinema, advertising etc. in order to depict certain human characteristics, and morally judge them. Despite that, the use of such animal stereotypes is generally considered less problematic than it is for human stereotypes.

"Man gave names to all the animals, in the beginning" says Bob Dilan in his song, meaning that animals were created by God, but the owner of their name in man, which gives him right to exploit them.

Using animals in media should be regulated by some kind of law, not only preventing cruelty, which was regulated 1939. after a horse was killed during the shooting of film "Jesse James" but also with some kind of ownership rights. If someone use image of an animal to promote some commercial product, the species used should benefit from it somehow.

Aware that "all characters are fictitious", even characters in documentary films, it would be nice anyway to see some animals in films that challenge common stereotypes, not by being better or worse, but by being more realistic. 


There is a list of most common stereotypes of animal characters:

Bats 
the bloodthirsty or evil bat

Bears 
the dumb bear, the cuddly, sweet bear

Bulls 
the aggressive bull who attacks everyone and everything with the color red

Cats 
The cool cat, the lazy cat, the evil/villainous cat

Dogs
the loyal dog, the dim-witted dog, the vicious bull dog

Donkeys 
the stubborn or stupid ass, the horny or virile donkey/stallion/bull

Elephants 
the unforgetting elephant, the mice-fearing elephant

Foxes 
the wily, cruel, cunning or intelligent fox

Hippopotamuses
the female hippopotamus who acts like a fat human lady

Horses 
the noble horse, the virile horse.

Hyenas 
the comical / always-laughing hyena, the cruel, bullying hyena

Kangaroos
the boxing kangaroo

Lemmings
the suicidal lemming

Lions
the proud, brave, noble or royal lion

Mice
the quiet mouse, the heroic mouse

Moles
the blind or near sighted mole

Moose
the slow-witted moose

Pigs
the greedy and/or filthy pig

Rabbits/Hares
the horny rabbit or hare, the hyperactive / fast-running rabbit / hare, the smart rabbit or hare

Raccoons
the criminal or scavenging raccoon

Rats
the evil or kleptomaniacal rat

Simians
the funny monkey/ape, the mischievous monkey, the monstrous or brutish ape (usually a gorilla), the amorous ape who lusts for human women

Skunks
the smelly skunk

Sloths
the lazy sloth

Squirrels
the hyperactive squirrel

Tigers
the vicious tiger

Weasels 
the sneaky and thieving weasel who always manages to flee.

Wolves
the cruel or evil wolf, the honorable wolf, the solitary or renegade wolf

Chickens
the stupid and or easily frightened chicken, the cock/rooster who has delusions of grandeur or is vain

Crows/Ravens 
the ominous raven or crow, the Afro-American crow

Ducks
the overconfident, arrogant duck who isn't as smart as he thinks.

Eagles
the child-stealing eagle, the proud, noble eagle

Geese
the gossipy goose[citation needed]

Magpies
the thieving magpie

Ostriches
the nervous ostrich

Owls 
the wise owl

Parrots
the talkative, annoying, and/or smartypants parrot/cockatoo (no distinction)

Peacocks
the proud peacock

Penguins 
the formal penguin

Pheasants 
the stupid, nervous pheasant

Storks
the baby-delivering stork

Crocodiles 
the weeping and hypocritical crocodile, the villainous crocodile

Dinosaurs
the fearsome, terrifying tyrannosaurus, the vicious, cunning Velociraptor

Frogs/Toads 
toads and frogs are often anthropomorphized into fat people.

Snakes 
the evil or untrustworthy snake

Turtles/Tortoises
the patient or slow-witted turtle / tortoise (No distinctions are generally made between the two.)

Dolphins
the joyful dolphin

Sharks 
the bloodthirsty shark

Whales 
the man-eating whale, the gentle whale or orca

Ants 
the diligent ant, the militant ant, the thieving/ bothersome ant.

Bees
the dopey (or "bumbling") bumblebee, the workaholic bumblebee

Crickets 
the cricket who plays violin

Grasshoppers 
the lazy / carefree grasshopper

Mantises 
the patient mantis

Spiders
the evil spider

Squid
the man eating monstrous giant squid who attacks and destroys ships

Termites
the destructive termite

Wasps 
the wanton and vicious wasp 

owl

Friday, June 3, 2011



- duels of characters in binary code: Moses vs. Aron -


In Schoenberg's opera Moses und Aron, which was put to the film by Jean-Marie Straub and Danielle Huillet, Moses represents idea, abstract word. Since people are unconvinced by Moses’s abstract words, Aron is here to give the people tangible proof in the form of miracles. However:



Images [would] lead and rule this folk
that you have freed,
and strange wishes [will be] their gods,
leading them back to the slavery
of godlessness and earthly pleasures.
You have betrayed God to the gods,
the idea to images,
this chosen folk to others,
the extraordinary to the commonplace... 



Moses accuses Aaron: "You...expose them to strange gods, to the calf and to the pillars of fire and cloud; for you do as the people do, because you feel and think as they do." In Schoenberg’s interpretation, this is why Aaron is bound to fail; it follows that when Aaron is set free, he falls down dead. Moses is left victorious to proclaim the ultimate goal: "Unity with God." 

The superstitious Schoenberg omitted the double “A” in Aaron so that the title would not contain 13 letters. This influenced a bit their duel in binary code:



Moses
01001101 01101111 01110011 01100101 01110011 
1 - 60% 
0 - 40% 
Aron
01000001 01110010 01101111 01101110 
1 - 53.1% 
0 - 46.9% 

Aaron
01000001 01100001 01110010 01101111 01101110 
1 - 50% 
0 - 50% 


In any case, Moses is victorious character, he has more 1 than 0 and wins both Aron and Aaron in this relation. However, by changing his name to Aron, Schoenberg made him to be stronger competitor for more than 3%.